Nash equilibrium
2008/9 Schools Wikipedia Selection. Related subjects: Mathematics
Nash Equilibrium | |
---|---|
A solution concept in game theory | |
Relationships | |
Subset of: | Rationalizability, Epsilon-equilibrium, Correlated equilibrium |
Superset of: | Evolutionarily stable strategy, Subgame perfect equilibrium, Perfect Bayesian equilibrium, Trembling hand perfect equilibrium |
Significance | |
Proposed by: | John Forbes Nash |
Used for: | All non-cooperative games |
Example: | Prisoner's dilemma |
In game theory, the Nash equilibrium (named after John Forbes Nash, who proposed it) is a solution concept of a game involving two or more players, in which no player has anything to gain by changing only his or her own strategy unilaterally. If each player has chosen a strategy and no player can benefit by changing his or her strategy while the other players keep theirs unchanged, then the current set of strategy choices and the corresponding payoffs constitute a Nash equilibrium.
Stated simply, Amy and Bill are in Nash equilibrium if Amy is making the best decision she can, taking into account Bill's decision, and Bill is making the best decision he can, taking into account Amy's decision. Likewise, many players are in Nash equilibrium if each one is making the best decision that they can, taking into account the decisions of the others. However, Nash equilibrium does not necessarily mean the best cumulative payoff for all the players involved; in many cases all the players might improve their payoffs if they could somehow agree on strategies different from the Nash equilibrium (eg. competing businessmen forming a cartel in order to increase their profits).
History
The concept of the Nash equilibrium (NE) is not entirely original to Nash (e.g., Antoine Augustin Cournot showed how to find what we now call the Nash equilibrium of the Cournot duopoly game). Consequently, some authors refer to it as a “Cournot-Nash equilibrium” (or as a “Nash-Cournot equilibrium”). However, Nash showed for the first time in his dissertation, Non-cooperative games( 1950), that Nash equilibria (in mixed strategies) must exist for all finite games with any number of players. Before Nash's work, this had only been proven for two-player zero-sum games (by John von Neumann and Oskar Morgenstern in 1947).
Definitions
Informal definition
Informally, a set of strategies is a Nash equilibrium if no player can do better by unilaterally changing his or her strategy. As a heuristic, one can imagine that each player is told the strategies of the other players. If any player would want to do something different after being informed about the others' strategies, then that set of strategies is not a Nash equilibrium. If, however, the player does not want to switch (or is indifferent between switching and not) then the set of strategies is a Nash equilibrium.
This can have counter-intuitive consequences. Since the Nash equilibrium focuses on an individual's preferences given that the others keep their choices fixed, there can be Nash equilibria where, if players could coordinate, they would all want to switch. The stag hunt presents an example of this phenomenon.
Formal definition
Let (S, f) be a game, where S is the set of strategy profiles and f is the set of payoff profiles. Let x − i be a strategy profile of all players except for player i. When each player chooses strategy xi resulting in strategy profile x = (x1,...,xn) then player i obtains payoff fi(x). Note that the payoff depends on the strategy profile chosen, i.e. on the strategy chosen by player i as well as the strategies chosen by all the other players. A strategy profile is a Nash equilibrium (NE) if no unilateral deviation in strategy by any single player is profitable, that is
A game can have a pure strategy NE or an NE in its mixed extension (that of choosing a pure strategy stochastically with a fixed frequency). Nash proved that, if we allow mixed strategies (players choose strategies randomly according to pre-assigned probabilities), then every n-player game in which every player can choose from finitely many strategies admits at least one Nash equilibrium.
Examples
Competition game
Player 2 chooses '0' | Player 2 chooses '1' | Player 2 chooses '2' | Player 2 chooses '3' | |
---|---|---|---|---|
Player 1 chooses '0' | 0, 0 | 2, -2 | 2, -2 | 2, -2 |
Player 1 chooses '1' | -2, 2 | 1, 1 | 3, -1 | 3, -1 |
Player 1 chooses '2' | -2, 2 | -1, 3 | 2, 2 | 4, 0 |
Player 1 chooses '3' | -2, 2 | -1, 3 | 0, 4 | 3, 3 |
This can be illustrated by a two-player game in which both players simultaneously choose a whole number from 0 to 3 and they both win the smaller of the two numbers in points. In addition, if one player chooses a larger number than the other, then he/she has to give up two points to the other. This game has a unique Nash equilibrium: both players choosing 0 (highlighted in light red). Any other choice of strategies can be improved if one of the players lowers his number to one less than the other player's number. In the table to the left, for example, when starting at the green square it is in player 1's interest to move to the purple square by choosing a smaller number, and it is in player 2's interest to move to the blue square by choosing a smaller number. If the game is modified so that the two players win the named amount if they both choose the same number, and otherwise win nothing, then there are 4 Nash equilibria (0,0...1,1...2,2...and 3,3).
Coordination game
Player 2 adopts strategy 1 | Player 2 adopts strategy 2 | |
---|---|---|
Player 1 adopts strategy 1 | A, A | B, C |
Player 1 adopts strategy 2 | C, B | D, D |
The coordination game is a classic ( symmetric) two player, two strategy game, with the payoff matrix shown to the right, where the payoffs satisfy A>C and D>B. The players should thus coordinate, either on A or on D, to receive a high payoff. If the players' choices do not coincide, a lower payoff is rewarded. An example of a coordination game is the setting where two technologies are available to two firms with compatible products, and they have to elect a strategy to become the market standard. If both firms agree on the chosen technology, high sales are expected for both firms. If the firms do not agree on the standard technology, few sales result. Both strategies are Nash equilibria of the game.
Driving on a road, and having to choose either to drive on the left or to drive on the right of the road, is also a coordination game. For example, with payoffs 100 meaning no crash and 0 meaning a crash, the coordination game can be defined with the following payoff matrix:
Drive on the Left | Drive on the Right | |
---|---|---|
Drive on the Left | 100, 100 | 0, 0 |
Drive on the Right | 0, 0 | 100, 100 |
In this case there are two pure strategy Nash equilibria, when both choose to either drive on the left or on the right. If we admit mixed strategies (where a pure strategy is chosen at random, subject to some fixed probability), then there are three Nash equilibria for the same case: two we have seen from the pure-strategy form, where the probabilities are (0%,100%) for player one, (0%, 100%) for player two; and (100%, 0%) for player one, (100%, 0%) for player two respectively. We add another where the probabilities for each player is (50%, 50%).
Prisoner's dilemma
- (but watch out for differences in the orientation of the payoff matrix)
The Prisoner's Dilemma has the same payoff matrix as depicted for the Coordination Game, but now C > A > D > B. Because C > A and D > B, each player improves his situation by switching from strategy #1 to strategy #2, no matter what the other player decides. The Prisoner's Dilemma thus has a single Nash Equilibrium: both players choosing strategy #2 ("betraying"). What has long made this an interesting case to study is the fact that D < A ("both betray") is globally inferior to "both remain loyal". The globally optimal strategy is unstable; it is not an equilibrium.
As Ian Stewart put it, "sometimes rational decisions aren't sensible!".
Nash equilibria in a payoff matrix
There is an easy numerical way to identify Nash Equilibria on a Payoff Matrix. It is especially helpful in two person games where players have more than two strategies. In this case formal analysis may become too long. This rule does not apply to the case where mixed (stochastic) strategies are of interest. The rule goes as follows: if the first payoff number, in the duplet of the cell, is the maximum of the column of the cell and if the second number is the maximum of the row of the cell - then the cell represents a Nash equilibrium.
We can apply this rule to a 3x3 matrix:
Option A | Option B | Option C | |
---|---|---|---|
Option A | 0, 0 | 25, 40 | 5, 10 |
Option B | 40, 25 | 0, 0 | 5, 15 |
Option C | 10, 5 | 15, 5 | 10, 10 |
Using the rule, we can very quickly (much faster than with formal analysis) see that the Nash Equlibria cells are (B,A), (A,B), and (C,C). Indeed, for cell (B,A) 40 is the maximum of the first column and 25 is the maximum of the second row. For (A,B) 25 is the maximum of the second column and 40 is the maximum of the first row. Same for cell (C,C). For other cells, either one or both of the duplet members are not the maximum of the corresponding rows and columns.
This said, the actual mechanics of finding equilibrium cells is obvious: find the maximum of a column and check if the second member of the pair is the maximum of the row. If these conditions are met, the cell represents a Nash Equilibrium. Check all columns this way to find all NE cells. An NxN matrix may have between 0 and NxN pure strategy Nash equilibria.
Stability
The concept of stability, useful in the analysis of many kinds of equilibrium, can also be applied to Nash equilibria.
A Nash equilibrium for a mixed strategy game is stable if a small change (specifically, an infinitesimal change) in probabilities for one player leads to a situation where two conditions hold:
- the player who did not change has no better strategy in the new circumstance
- the player who did change is now playing with a strictly worse strategy
If these cases are both met, then a player with the small change in his mixed-strategy will return immediately to the Nash equilibrium. The equilibrium is said to be stable. If condition one does not hold then the equilibrium is unstable. If only condition one holds then there are likely to be an infinite number of optimal strategies for the player who changed. John Nash showed that the latter situation could not arise in a range of well-defined games.
In the "driving game" example above there are both stable and unstable equilibria. The equilibria involving mixed-strategies with 100% probabilities are stable. If either player changes his probabilities slightly, they will be both at a disadvantage, and his opponent will have no reason to change his strategy in turn. The (50%,50%) equilibrium is unstable. If either player changes his probabilities, then the other player immediately has a better strategy at either (0%, 100%) or (100%, 0%).
Stability is crucial in practical applications of Nash equilibria, since the mixed-strategy of each player is not perfectly known, but has to be inferred from statistical distribution of his actions in the game. In this case unstable equilibria are very unlikely to arise in practice, since any minute change in the proportions of each strategy seen will lead to a change in strategy and the breakdown of the equilibrium.
Note that stability of the equilibrium is related to, but distinct from, stability of a strategy.
A Coalition-Proof Nash Equilibrium (CPNE) (similar to a Strong Nash Equilibrium) occurs when players cannot do better even if they are allowed to communicate and collaborate before the game. Every correlated strategy supported by iterated strict dominance and on the Pareto frontier is a CPNE. Further, it is possible for a game to have a Nash equilibrium that is resilient against coalitions less than a specified size, k. CPNE is related to the theory of the core.
Occurrence
If a game has a unique Nash equilibrium and is played among players under certain conditions, then the NE strategy set will be adopted. Sufficient conditions to guarantee that the Nash equilibrium is played are:
- The players all will do their utmost to maximize their expected payoff as described by the game.
- The players are flawless in execution.
- The players have sufficient intelligence to deduce the solution.
- There is common knowledge that all players meet these conditions, including this one. So, not only must each player know the other players meet the conditions, but also they must know that they all know that they meet them, and know that they know that they know that they meet them, and so on.
Where the conditions are not met
Examples of game theory problems in which these conditions are not met:
- The first condition is not met if the game does not correctly describe the quantities a player wishes to maximize. In this case there is no particular reason for that player to adopt an equilibrium strategy. For instance, the prisoner’s dilemma is not a dilemma if either player is happy to be jailed indefinitely.
- Intentional or accidental imperfection in execution. For example, a computer capable of flawless logical play facing a second flawless computer will result in equilibrium. Introduction of imperfection will lead to its disruption either through loss to the player who makes the mistake, or through negation of the 4th 'common knowledge' criterion leading to possible victory for the player. (An example would be a player suddenly putting the car into reverse in the game of 'chicken', ensuring a no-loss no-win scenario). A notable example of this situation in fiction is the Doctor Who serial Destiny of the Daleks
- In many cases, the third condition is not met because, even though the equilibrium must exist, it is unknown due to the complexity of the game, for instance in Chinese chess. Or, if known, it may not be known to all players, as when playing tic-tac-toe with a small child who desperately wants to win (meeting the other criteria).
- The fourth criterion of common knowledge may not be met even if all players do, in fact, meet all the other criteria. Players wrongly distrusting each other's rationality may adopt counter-strategies to expected irrational play on their opponents’ behalf. This is a major consideration in “ Chicken” or an arms race, for example.
Where the conditions are met
Due to the limited conditions in which NE can actually be observed, they are rarely treated as a guide to day-to-day behaviour, or observed in practice in human negotiations. However, as a theoretical concept in economics, and evolutionary biology the NE has explanatory power. The payoff in economics is money, and in evolutionary biology gene transmission, both are the fundamental bottom line of survival. Researchers who apply games theory in these fields claim that agents failing to maximize these for whatever reason will be competed out of the market or environment, which are ascribed the ability to test all strategies. This conclusion is drawn from the " stability" theory above. In these situations the assumption that the strategy observed is actually a NE has often been borne out by research.
Proof of existence
As above, let σ − i be a mixed strategy profile of all players except for player i. We can define a best response correspondence for player i, bi. bi is a relation from the set of all probability distributions over opponent player profiles to a set of player i's strategies, such that each element of
- bi(σ − i)
is a best response to σ − i. Define
- .
One can use the Kakutani fixed point theorem to prove that b has a fixed point. That is, there is a σ * such that . Since b(σ * ) represents the best response for all players to σ * , the existence of the fixed point proves that there is some strategy set which is a best response to itself. No player could do any better by deviating, and it is therefore a Nash equilibrium.
When Nash made this point to John von Neumann in 1949, von Neumann famously dismissed it with the words, "That's trivial, you know. That's just a fixed point theorem." (See Nasar, 1998, p. 94.)